While reading through a book by Martha Nussbaum, recommended
to me by a friend, I thought of something. Sometimes it feels to me as though philosophy
comes in two basic forms.
One form is what I’ll call Philosophical Exposition. This, I believe, is what most people have
in mind when they think of philosophy. In this form, philosophical arguments come
in the form of a strong argument for something. The writer makes a claim, lays
out an argument, supports the argument with some combination of reasoning and
evidence, and underscores a particular conclusion. Obviously, this form of
exposition isn’t particularly unique to philosophy; most formal writing looks
like this, and even a great deal of conversation unfolds in this way.
The other form of philosophy is what I’ll call Philosophical Prose, and from what I
can tell, it is largely unique to philosophy. In Philosophical Prose, the
writer decides that, rather than outline a full argument for something, he or
she would rather sketch out a rough idea that merely sounds good, without
having to go through the rigor of formally arguing for it. The goal of this
kind of philosophy is not to set out a forthright conclusion, but rather to
provide a nice-sounding piece of writing that draws the reader in. Repeated exposure
to philosophy of this kind, when the ideas all point in the same direction,
will have the effect of slowly wearing down a critic’s resistance to an idea, until
there is such a large body of text promoting
a given philosophical idea that no real argument for it seems necessary
anymore.
Providing examples of Philosophical Exposition seems like a
superfluous exercise. We all know what formal exposition looks like, and we can
all cite examples. Anyway, by now it should be rather obvious that the point of
the current post is to examine and criticize Philosophical Prose. So, let’s
take a look at some examples of that.
The ugliest example I can think of is any statement that
comes in the form “Any X properly Y ought to be Z.” One might argue, for instance,
that “any theory of equality properly defined ought to include a concept
of social justice.” When writers make statements like these, they are simply
being lazy, skipping the hard work of, in this case, defining a theory of
equality that actually does what the writer wants it to do. Instead of doing
that work, the writer simply makes a normative declaration, viz. that equality “ought
to” include social justice, and leaves the actual argumentation to others. This
is a tempting approach to philosophy since the power of such a statement is
that it simply refusing to acknowledge any dissent, whether it exists or not. If
we were to take such statements seriously – and we ought not – we’d realize
that they are really just No True Scotsman fallacies in so many words.
Another one of Philosophical Prose’s dirty tricks involves
skipping the hard work entirely. The
writer might say, “Making a thorough justification for neoliberalism is a
necessary task, but it is beyond the scope of the present work. For now, I will
simply argue that neoliberalism, once accepted, should be applied universally
across all political systems.” In other words, the writer wants to go to the
fun part of having a good theory, which is telling everyone that they ought to
agree with how wonderful that theory is, but the writer doesn’t want to have to
be bothered to undertake the actual task of effectively arguing for that
theory.
As is implied by the first sentence of this blog post, my
impression of Marth Nussbaum’s work thus far – not having read very much of it,
but having gotten a decent taste of it – is that it is more Philosophical Prose
than Philosophical Exposition. This fact certainly weakens the persuasiveness
of her arguments, at least among those readers who are looking for reasons to
believe a particular thing.
But, on the other hand, I don’t believe Nussbaum’s target audience
consists of people like that. Instead, I think Nussbaum writes for people who
already agree with her, and who want to experience a sense of rapture from
reading emotional, normative statements like “Any X properly Y ought to be Z,”
followed by many paragraphs of the normative value of Z among a particularly
needy group of would-be beneficiaries. Such Philosophical Prose is sure to
strengthen conviction among the already-converted, and so in that sense it
serves a worthy purpose.
However, we must keep in mind that the worthy purpose served
by Philosophical Prose is something other than arguing for truth; it’s
something more like preaching a religion.
No comments:
Post a Comment