For quite some time now, there has been a mild debate about “thick”
versus “thin” libertarianism. “Thin” libertarianism is the belief that
libertarianism at its essence only defines humankind’s relationship to the
state, nothing more. “Thick” libertarianism is a belief system that aims to
extend libertarian thought to non-state situations. I’d like to explore these
concepts a little bit, but before I do, let’s make sure we understand the
difference between thick and thin.
Consider the issue of feminism, since it highlights the
difference quite nicely. A thin libertarian believes that the state ought to
treat people of all genders equally under the law. And that’s it. A thick
libertarian, by contrast, believes that equal treatment under the law is only
part of the story. Meanwhile, women may face coercive non-state pressure from
the “Patriarchy” more broadly, and that libertarianism ought to respond to this
pressure in some way. For example, a young woman might experience unwanted pressure
from family members or religious community members to marry and have children.
While a thin libertarian has no specific comment on this, since the coercive
pressure isn’t coming from the government, a thick libertarian wants to be this
young woman’s ally. A thick libertarian wants to articulate philosophical
reasons why this woman shouldn’t be coerced into a lifestyle she might not
choose. A thick libertarian believes that such coercive social pressure limits
a woman’s freedom even though there is no state involvement; and thus, if we’re
“truly” concerned about liberty, we ought to advocate against this sort of
coercive social pressure in addition to
coercive pressure against the state.
A thin libertarian might agree with the thick libertarian in theory. That is, the thin libertarian
might agree that such social pressure is bad. But the thin libertarian draws a
line between political and non-political life. A thin libertarian might say
something like this: “As a libertarian, I have no comment on such social
pressure, but as a feminist it offends me and I believe it is wrong.”
On the other hand, a thin libertarian also has the
flexibility to say something like this, “Young women ought to get married and
have children, but as long as the state does not coerce her, it is not a
libertarian issue.”
From this, we ought to be able to understand a major source
of libertarian infighting. Thin libertarianism allows libertarians to engage in
private coercive behavior that would be abhorrent (to libertarians) if/when
conducted by the state. Thick libertarianism is opposed to that same behavior,
no matter who is doing it. This has given rise to situations in which people
with bigoted or possibly-bigoted views gravitate toward thin libertarianism because
it enables them to maintain their bigotry, so long as it is confined to private
matters, while thick libertarians accuse thin libertarians of “harboring” or “enabling”
that same bigotry.
If you’re with me so far, then you now understand much of
what the libertarian community has been arguing about for the past year or so,
especially in light of the recent protests in Charleston and elsewhere.
Now that we know what libertarianism is, we’ll next consider what libertarianism ought to be.
If you’re with me so far, then you now understand much of what the libertarian community has been arguing about for the past year or so, especially in light of the recent protests in Charleston and elsewhere.
ReplyDeletedesigns for cricut
cricut joy tutorial
what is cricut vinyl used for
valentines day card cricut
template for cricut
badass cricut projects